The view sometimes assigned to sociobiologists, or evolutionary psychologists, that we must follow our genetic blueprints, gains traction from the analogies drawn to illustrate their ideas, such as Dawkins’s ‘lumbering robots’. This inference is unfair, since they do accept cultural influence on behaviour, but, relevant to this question, they would expect the sexes to have evolved differently (even competitively) because of their differing physical characteristics. Women have larger sex cells than men, and carry the foetus for nine months. Because men can afford more reproductions in a lifetime, sociobiology would suggest that emotions would evolve differently to motivate men to spend more than women; i.e., have more promiscuous tendencies. Does this mean that some of the more rabid accusations aimed at evolutionary psychology are true? If we consider this statement, typical of the sort of thing:
If gene-machine Darwinism is true, then we cannot blame a man for sexual infidelity, nor praise a woman for being faithful.To tease out the implications of this conditional statement, we can consider it the outline of an argument, with the antecedent as the premise and the consequent as the conclusion:
Premise
|
Men’s
genes give them a tendency to sexual infidelity
|
Conclusion
|
Men cannot be blamed for
sexual infidelity
|
This is invalid; there is a hidden premise or two. We could complete it like this:
Premise 1
|
Men’s
genes give them a tendency to sexual infidelity
|
Premise 2
|
Men cannot be blamed for their tendencies
|
Conclusion
|
Men cannot be blamed for
sexual infidelity
|
This looks valid, although there is a slight equivocation on the
word ‘men’. Not all men will have a
tendency equally, so we cannot conclude that all men are blameless for sexual infidelity. But we’ll pass on this and assume ‘men’
refers to the average man.
The implication of P2 is that our tendencies are overwhelming in
their force. This doesn’t seem to be true at all. We are all aware of
temptations and understand we can resist
them. In such circumstances, other inclinations and reasoning help us to resist. Sociobiology claims we are a basket
of competing traits and tools evolved for dealing with the world, and it’s too
simplistic to say we blindly follow
our tendencies. And to say we blindly follow one tendency, such as a sexual imperative, is even more so. The law
recognises in cases of diminished responsibility that in some circumstances,
including natural aberrations, we cannot be held wholly responsible for our
actions. But this principle acknowledges that the average person is responsible for their actions, and
it’s the average person we’re
considering.
The ‘gene-machine’ charge might be levelled by a 'blank-paperist' (a
believer in the social science model that holds that a
large part of our nature derives from the cultural environment), in which case we can ask if their counter position can be justified. This would have to look something like this:
P1
|
People’s
behaviour is determined by their culture
|
P2
|
People
determine their culture
|
P3
|
People
can be blamed for what they determine
|
Conclusion
|
People can be blamed for
their behaviour
|
Some say that people do
determine their cultural environment. In a sense, that’s true about their
current situation. But the development of traits that occur pre-adulthood is
inaccessible to us as adults. Many traits form in the years before 16, so there
may be an opportunity for the blank-paperist to determine them in childhood
that is not available to the gene-machinist. That may be relevant to the wider
community, but no individual, contra
P2, can determine their own culture
in their formative years. And there is no reason to believe that how these traits are formed makes them
more or less mutable in adulthood.
So, once determined, however that may be, the problem of blame
presents itself. To determine one’s own traits, one would have to exist prior
to one’s own conception – a logical impossibility. So determinism seems to be the
enemy of blame, not genetic
determinism.
Looking at P3, we do blame people for what they do, often ignoring
prior causes. This arises from a sense of localised
or ordinary responsibility because, perhaps,
it’s more important to understand immediate
causes. Consider a house underneath a cliff that suffers from rock-falls. If the
rock-falls are due to an unstable rock face, the instability can be addressed.
If they’re due to someone pushing rocks down, then they should be held
responsible and prevented from re-offending. Observing that, ultimately, both
the unstable rock face and the vandal are simply following causes deterministically as
part of one long chain of causality from the Big Bang doesn’t help us to decide a future
course of action.
Consequentialists and deontologists would take different approaches
to the vandal; the consequentialist would see little value in blame unless it resulted in greater
benefits than other responses. Deontologists would lay blame because of the
inherent wrongness of the act. But neither
would blame, morally, the unstable rock face for falling on the house, because
it lacks agency. If agency is a temporary phenomenon, it would not be
appropriate to say that someone is, or is not, ultimately to blame, but to say that they are locally to blame is pragmatic. We recognise prior agencies as
mitigating factors; if the miscreant has been unduly influenced by another, for
example. But the further back from the current moment we move the less
responsibility we assign. So the passage of time is relevant to the level of responsibility, in conjunction with
agency, and neither rests on the truth of gene-machine Darwinism.
The charge from immaterialists,
typically theists, is that determinism
follows from materialism (immateriality is redundant in gene-machine Darwinism).
Science suggests that materialism may not entail determinism, but we’ll allow
this assumption for the sake of argument. Immaterialists suggest that morality is meaningless without ‘free’
choice; if our actions follow unavoidably
from prior events, blame cannot be laid:
P1
|
Materialism
entails determinism
|
P2
|
Determinism
dictates that every cause has a prior cause
|
P3
|
Responsibility
rests where the causal chain stops; at a cause without a prior cause
|
Conclusion
|
Materialism precludes
responsibility
|
We blame the person responsible,
but if the causal chain doesn’t stop, neither does the responsibility. The
argument looks valid; P1 we are allowing, P2 is just determinism defined, but
P3 looks suspect. As discussed above, a local responsibility is understandable, even with a chain of events extending back into
the past to other ultimate causes. In
fact, to rest the responsibility where there are no prior causes can prevent us laying blame. Consider the
following scenario: a woman sees a man advancing toward a baby with his arms
outstretched. She hits him with her handbag, knocking him out. Among the reasons for her actions could be:
a)
She knew the man meant to harm
the baby.
b)
She’s a lunatic out to hit the
first man she sees.
c)
She made the decision to hit
the man, or acted to hit the man, with no prior cause.
The first two explanations allow us to draw on further evidence and perhaps
assign praise (a) or blame (b, with diminished responsibility). But (c) leaves
us helpless, because intentions are a
major factor in moral judgements. Indeterministic acts happen for no reason. Further, it’s hard to see why someone could do
something without prior cause; how would they know what to do without the
knowledge of the situation? Perhaps knowledge of the situation exists, but does
not count as a prior cause? But the woman is hitting the man because he’s there, else she’d be
flailing at nothing. It is a necessary precursor to the act, so must be a
component of some prior cause. So indeterminism
stops us placing blame, and gene-machine Darwinism is not to blame for that!
The expanded argument for the second part of the conditional we're considering shares the
same problems:
P1
|
Women’s
genes give them a tendency to sexual constancy
|
P2
|
People
cannot be praised for their tendencies
|
Conclusion
|
Women cannot be blamed
for sexual constancy
|
The implication is we have no
choice but to follow our tendencies. To expand further:
P1
|
Women’s
genes give them a tendency to sexual constancy
|
P2
|
People
have no choice but to follow their tendencies
|
P3
|
People
should only be praised for choosing
to act well
|
P4
|
Sexual
constancy is acting well
|
Conclusion
|
Women cannot be praised
for sexual constancy
|
P2 is false per gene-machinists, but P3 is troublesome too. Comedian
Richard Herring cracks the joke “I was very moral as a teenager; I was a virgin
by choice, but also because no-one would have sex with me.” We recognise a
difference between acting well by choice rather than by circumstance (imagine
if Herring's setup was that he was trying to be promiscuous, but failing). But the charge against
gene-machine Darwinism is a little deeper than this; it’s the suggestion that we
have no choice because of our nature and
cannot choose to act well, so never
act well. But we hear stories of people acting ‘heroically’ and afterwards saying
‘I had no time to think’ or ‘It all happened so quick’. Heroes often act
instinctively, not through choice,
but we think they are praiseworthy still. We praise them because of the nature that compelled them; the hero could have done otherwise in a way that
the rock from the previous example could not, but didn’t, and wouldn’t. The idea that they might do
something else in the same circumstances would just make their actions arbitrary, and them unreliable, which would hardly attract plaudits. Natural compulsion, then, doesn’t
preclude praise, and gene-machine Darwinism’s supposed denial of choice is not
fatal to praise-giving, either.
Whether we can praise or blame, then, may still be an issue, but the
fact of it does not turn on the truth
of so-called gene-machine Darwinism. The arguments to support the conditional could be
constructed differently, so we have not exhausted all possible justifications.
Nevertheless, based on the arguments considered above, it's clear that the implications often ascribed to ultra Darwinism are quite unwarranted. Ultimately, all that it argues for is the origin of personality traits, not their strength or immutability. As Dawkins says in The Extended Phenotype, when he complains about the unjustified reputation that genes have acquired as 'sinister' and 'juggernaut-like':
Educational, or other cultural influences may, in some circumstances, be just as unmodifiable and irreversible as genes and ‘stars’ are popularly thought to be.
Quite.
Bibliography:
Radcliffe-Richards, J. (2000) Human Nature After Darwin (A211 Book 4), Milton Keynes, The Open University
Bibliography:
Radcliffe-Richards, J. (2000) Human Nature After Darwin (A211 Book 4), Milton Keynes, The Open University
0 comments:
Post a Comment